Ramsey cardinals were introduced by Erdős and Hajnal in {% cite Erdoes1962 %}. Their consistency strength lies strictly between $0^\sharp$ and measurable cardinals. There are many Ramsey-like cardinals with strength between weakly compact and measurable cardinals inclusively. {% cite Feng1990 Gitman2011 Sharpe2011 Holy2018 Nielsen2018 %} ## Ramsey cardinals ### Definitions A cardinal $\kappa$ is Ramsey if it has the [[partition property]] $\kappa\rightarrow (\kappa)^{\lt\omega}_2$. For infinite cardinals $\kappa$ and $\lambda$, the [](Partition%20property.md) $\kappa\to(\lambda)^n_\gamma$ asserts that for every function $F:\[\kappa\]^n\to\gamma$ there is $H\subseteq\kappa$ with $\|H\|=\lambda$ such that $F\upharpoonright\[H\]^n$ is constant. Here $\[X\]^n$ is the set of all $n$-elements subsets of $X$. The more general partition property $\kappa\to(\lambda)^{\lt\omega}_\gamma$ asserts that for every function $F:\[\kappa\]^{\lt\omega}\to\gamma$ there is $H\subseteq\kappa$ with $\|H\|=\lambda$ such that $F\upharpoonright\[H\]^n$ is constant for every $n$, although the value of $F$ on $\[H\]^n$ may be different for different $n$. Indeed, if $\kappa$ is Ramsey, then $\kappa\rightarrow (\kappa)^{\lt\omega}_\lambda$ for every $\lambda<\kappa$. Ramsey cardinals were named in honor of Frank Ramsey, whose Ramsey theorem for partition properties of $\omega$ motivated the generalizations of these to uncountable cardinals. A Ramsey cardinal $\kappa$ is exactly the [$\kappa$-Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") cardinal. Ramsey cardinals have a number of other characterizations. They may be characterized model theoretically through the existence of $\kappa$-sized sets of indiscernibles for models meeting the criteria discussed below, as well as through the existence of $\kappa$-sized models of set theory without power set with iterable [ultrapowers](Ultrapower.md "Ultrapower"). **Indiscernibles**: Suppose $\mathcal A=(A,\ldots)$ is a model of a language $\mathcal L$ of size less than $\kappa$ whose universe $A$ contains $\kappa$ as a subset. If a cardinal $\kappa$ is Ramsey, then every such model $\mathcal A$ has a $\kappa$-sized set of indiscernibles $H\subseteq\kappa$, that is, for every formula $\varphi(\overline x)$ of $\mathcal L$ and every pair of tuples $\overline \alpha$ and $\overline \beta$ of elements of $H$, we have $\mathcal A\models\varphi (\overline \alpha)\leftrightarrow \varphi(\overline \beta)$. {% cite Jech2003 %} **Good sets of indiscernibles**: Suppose $A\subseteq\kappa$ and $L_\kappa\[A\]$ denotes the $\kappa^{\text{th}}$-level of the universe constructible using a predicate for $A$. A set $I\subseteq\kappa$ is a good set of indiscernibles for the model $\langle L_\kappa\[A\],A\rangle$ if for all $\gamma\in I$, - $\langle L_\gamma\[A\cap \gamma\],A\cap \gamma\rangle\prec \langle L_\kappa\[A\], A\rangle$, - $I\setminus\gamma$ is a set of indiscernibles for the model $\langle L_\kappa\[A\], A,\xi\rangle_{\xi\in\gamma}$. A cardinal $\kappa$ is Ramsey if and only if for every $A\subseteq\kappa$, there is a $\kappa$-sized good set of indiscernibles for the model $\langle L_\kappa\[A\], A\rangle$. {% cite Dodd1981 %} **$M$-<a href="Ultrafilter" class="mw-redirect" title="Ultrafilter">ultrafilters</a>**: Suppose a transitive $M\models {\rm ZFC}^-$, the theory ${\rm ZFC}$ without the power set axiom (and using collection and separation rather than merely replacement) and $\kappa$ is a cardinal in $M$. We call $U\subseteq P(\kappa)^M$ an $M$-ultrafilter if the model $\langle M,U\rangle\models$“$U$ is a normal ultrafilter on $\kappa$”. In the case when the $M$-ultrafilter is not an element of $M$, the model $\langle M,U\rangle$ of $M$ together with a predicate for $U$ often fails to satisfy much of ${\rm ZFC}$. An $M$-ultrafilter $U$ is said to be weakly amenable (to $M$) if for every $A\in M$ of size $\kappa$ in $M$, the intersection $A\cap U$ is an element of $M$. An $M$-ultrafilter $U$ is countably complete if every countable sequence (possibly external to $M$) of elements of $U$ has a non-empty intersection (even if the intersection is not itself an element of $M$). A weak $\kappa$-model is a transitive set $M\models {\rm ZFC}^- $ of size $\kappa$ and containing $\kappa$ as an element. A modified ultrapower construction using only functions on $\kappa$ that are elements of $M$ can be carried out with an $M$-ultrafilter. If the $M$-ultrafilter happens to be countably complete, then the standard argument shows that the ultrapower is well-founded. If the $M$-ultrafilter is moreover weakly amenable, then a weakly amenable ultrafilter on the image of $\kappa$ in the well-founded ultrapower can be constructed from images of the pieces of $U$ that are in $M$. The ultrapower construction may be iterated in this manner, taking direct limits at limit stages, and in this case the countable completeness of the $M$-ultrafilter ensures that every stage of the iteration produces a well-founded model. {% cite Kanamori2009 %} (Ch. 19) A cardinal $\kappa$ is Ramsey if and only if every $A\subseteq\kappa$ is contained in a weak $\kappa$-model $M$ for which there exists a weakly amenable countably complete $M$-ultrafilter on $\kappa$. {% cite Dodd1981 %} ### Ramsey cardinals and the constructible universe Ramsey cardinals imply that <a href="Zero_sharp" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero sharp">$0^\sharplt;/a> exists and hence there cannot be Ramsey cardinals in $L$. {% cite Kanamori2009 %} ### Relations with other large cardinals - [Measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinals are Ramsey and stationary limits of Ramsey cardinals. {% cite Erdoes1962 %} - Ramsey cardinals are [unfoldable](Unfoldable.md "Unfoldable") (using the $M$-ultrafilters characterization) and stationary limits of unfoldable cardinals (as they are stationary limits of $\omega_1$-iterable cardinals). - Ramsey cardinals are stationary limits of <a href="Completely_ineffable" class="mw-redirect" title="Completely ineffable">completely ineffable</a> cardinals, they are <a href="Weakly_ineffable" class="mw-redirect" title="Weakly ineffable">weakly ineffable</a>, but the least Ramsey cardinal is not ineffable. Ineffable Ramsey cardinals are limits of Ramsey cardinals, because ineffable cardinals are $Π^1_2$-indescribable and being Ramsey is a $Π^1_2$-statement.{% cite Gitman2011 %} - There are stationarily many completely ineffable, [](Erdos.md) cardinals below any Ramsey cardinal.{% cite Sharpe2011 %} Weaker Ramsey-like: - The existence of a Ramsey cardinal is stronger than the existence of a proper class of almost Ramsey cardinals. - The Ramsey cardinals are precisely the [Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") almost Ramsey cardinals and also precisely the [[weakly compact]] almost Ramsey cardinals. - A Ramsey cardinal is $\omega_1$-iterable and a stationary limit of $\omega_1$-iterable cardinals. This is already true of an $\omega_1$-[Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") cardinal. {% cite Sharpe2011 %} - A virtually Ramsey cardinal that is [[weakly compact]] is already Ramsey. If $κ$ is Ramsey, then there is a forcing extension destroying this, while preserving that $κ$ is virtually Ramsey. It is open whether virtually Ramsey cardinals are weaker than Ramsey cardinals. {% cite Gitman2011a Gitman %} Stronger Ramsey-like: - If $κ$ is $Π_1$-Ramsey, then the set of Ramsey cardinals less then $κ$ is in the $Π_1$-Ramsey filter on $κ$.{% cite Feng1990 %} - Strongly Ramsey cardinals are Ramsey and stationary limits of Ramsey cardinals.{% cite Gitman2011 %} - Mahlo–Ramsey cardinals are a direct strengthening of Ramseyness.{% cite Sharpe2011 %} ### Ramsey cardinals and forcing - Ramsey cardinals are preserved by small forcing. {% cite Kanamori2009 %} - Ramsey cardinals $\kappa$ are preserved by the canonical forcing of the ${\rm GCH}$, by fast function forcing, and by the forcing to add a slim $\kappa$-Kurepa tree. {% cite Gitman %} - If $\kappa$ is Ramsey, there is a forcing extension in which $\kappa$ remains Ramsey and $2^\kappa\gt\kappa$. {% cite Gitman Cody2015 %} - If the ${\rm GCH}$ holds and $F$ is a class function on the regular cardinals having a closure point at $\kappa$ and satisfying $F(\alpha)\leq F(\beta)$ for $\alpha<\beta$ and $\text{cf}(F(\alpha))>\alpha$, then there is a cofinality preserving forcing extension in which $\kappa$ remains Ramsey and $2^\delta=F(\delta)$ for every regular cardinal $\delta$. {% cite Cody2015 %} - There is a forcing extension in which $κ$ is the first cardinal at which the $\mathrm{GCH}$ fails. {% cite Gitman %} - If the existence of Ramsey cardinals is consistent with ZFC, then there is a model of ZFC in which $\kappa$ is not Ramsey, but becomes Ramsey in a forcing extension. {% cite Gitman %} ## Completely Romsey cardinals etc. (All information in this section are from {% cite Feng1990 %} unless otherwise noted) ### Basic definitions - $\mathcal{P}(x)$ is the powerset (set of all subsets) of $x$. $\mathcal{P}_k(x)$ is the set of all subsets of $x$ with exactly $k$ elements. - $f:\mathcal{P}_k(λ) \to λ$ is regressive iff for all $A \in \mathcal{P}_k(λ)$, we have $f(A) < \min(A)$. - $E$ is $f$-homogenous iff $E \subseteq λ$ and for all $B,C \in \mathcal{P}_k(E)$, we have $f(B) = f(C)$. ### $Π_α$-Ramsey and completely Ramsey Suppose that $κ$ is a regular uncountable cardinal and $I \supseteq \mathcal{P}_{<κ}(κ)$ is an ideal on $κ$. For every $X \subseteq $κ, $X \in \mathcal{R}^+(I)$ iff for every regressive function $f:\mathcal{P}_{<ω}(κ) \to κ$, for every club $C \subseteq κ$, there is a $Y \in I^+f$ such that $Y \subseteq X \cap C$ and $Y$ is homogeneous for $f$. $\mathcal{R}(I) = \mathcal{P}(κ) - \mathcal{R}^+(I)$ $\mathcal{R}^*(I) = \{ X \subseteq κ : κ - X \in \mathcal{R}(I) \}$ A regular uncountable cardinal $κ$ is Ramsey iff $κ \not\in \mathcal{R}(\mathcal{P}_{<κ}(κ))$. If it is Ramsey, we call $\mathcal{R}(\mathcal{P}_{<κ}(κ))$ *the Ramsey <a href="Ideal" class="mw-redirect" title="Ideal">ideal</a>* on $κ$, its dual $\mathcal{R}^*(\mathcal{P}_{<κ}(κ))$ *the Ramsey [filter](Filter.md "Filter")* and every element of $\mathcal{R}^+(\mathcal{P}_{<κ}(κ))$ *a Ramsey subset* of $κ$. For a regular uncountable cardinal $κ$, we define - $I_{-2}^κ = \mathcal{P}_{<κ}(κ)$ - $I_{-1}^κ = NS_κ$ (the set of non-stationary subsets of $κ$) - for $n < ω$, $I_n^κ = \mathcal{R}(I_{n-2}^κ)$ - for $α \geq ω$, $I_{α+1}^κ = \mathcal{R}(I_α^κ)$ - for limit ordinal $γ$, $I_γ^κ = \bigcup_{β<γ} \mathcal{R}(I_β^κ)$ Regular uncountable cardinal $κ$ is **$Π_α$-Ramsey** iff $κ \not\in I_α^κ$ and **completely Ramsey** iff for all $α$, $κ \not\in I_α^κ$. If $κ$ is $Π_α$-Ramsey, we call $I_α^κ$ *the $Π_α$-Ramsey ideal* on $κ$, its dual *the $Π_α$-Ramsey filter* and every subset of $κ$ not in $I_α^κ$ *a $Π_α$-Ramsey subset*. If $κ$ is completely Ramsey, we call $I_{θ_κ}^κ$ *the completely Ramsey ideal* on $κ$, its dual *the completely Ramsey filter* and every subset of $κ$ not in $I_{θ_κ}^κ$ *a completely Ramsey subset*. ($θ_κ$ is the least $α$ such that $I_α^κ = I_{α+1}^κ$ — it must exist before $(2^κ)^+$ <span class="small">for every regular uncountable $κ$ — even if the ideals are trivial</span>) ### $α$-hyper completely Ramsey and super completely Ramsey A sequence $⟨f_α:α<κ^+⟩$ of elements of $^κκ$ is a *canonical sequence* on $κ$ if both - for all $α, β\in κ$, $α < β$ implies $f_α < f_β$. - and for any other sequence $⟨g_α:α<κ^+⟩$ of elements of $κ^κ$ such that $\forall_{α < β < κ^κ} g_α < g_β$, we have $\forall_{α < κ^+} f_α < g_α$. Note four facts: - If $⟨f_α:α<κ^+⟩$ and $⟨g_α:α<κ^+⟩$ both are canonical sequences on $κ$, then for all $α < κ^+$ there is a club $C_α \subseteq κ$ such that $\forall_{γ \in C_α} f_α(γ) = g_α(γ)$. (*All pairs of corresponding elements of two sequences of functions are equal on a club.*) - There are canonical sequences on each regular uncountable cardinal. - If $⟨h_α:α<κ^+⟩$ is a canonical sequence on $κ$, then for all $α < κ^+$ there is a club $C_α \subseteq κ$ such that $\forall_{η \in C_α} h_α(η) < \|η\|^+$. (*Each function in a sequence takes on a club values with cardinality not greater then argument's.*) - For all $β < κ^+$ there is a club $C_β \subseteq κ$ such that for all uncountable regular $λ \in C_β$, the set $\{ γ < λ : f^λ_{f^κ_β(λ)}(γ) = f^κ_β(γ) \}$ contains a club in $λ$, where $\vec {f^λ}$ and $\vec {f^κ}$ are canonical sequences on $λ$ and $κ$ respectively. For a regular uncountable cardinal $κ$, let $\vec f = ⟨f_α:α<κ^+⟩$ be the canonical sequence on $κ$. - $κ$ is **0-hyper completely Ramsey** iff $κ$ is completely Ramsey. - For $α<κ^+$, $κ$ is **$α+1$-hyper completely Ramsey** iff $κ$ is $α$-hyper completely Ramsey and there is a completely Ramsey subset $X$ such that for all $λ \in X$, $λ$ is $f_α(λ)$-hyper completely Ramsey. - For $γ \leq κ^+$, $κ$ is **$γ$-hyper completely Ramsey** iff $κ$ is $β$-hyper completely Ramsey for all $β<γ$. - $κ$ is **super completely Ramsey** iff $κ$ is $κ^+$-hyper completely Ramsey. ### Terminology (This subsection compares (Sharpe&Welch, 2011) and (Feng, 1990)) $Π_α$-Ramsey cardinals correspond to $α$-Ramsey and $α$-Ramsey$^s$ in {% cite Sharpe2011 Holy2018 %} (The “$^s$” stands for “stationary”.{% cite Sharpe2011 %}) $Π_{2 n}$-Ramsey cardinals are Sharpe-Welch $n$-Ramsey and $Π_{2 n + 1}$-Ramsey cardinals are $n$-Ramsey$^s$. For infinite $α$, $Π_α$-Ramsey, Sharpe-Welch $α$-Ramsey and $α$-Ramsey$^s$ are identical. ### Results Absoluteness: - All this properties (being Ramsey itself, $Π_α$-Ramsey, completely Ramsey, $α$-hyper completely Ramsey and super completely Ramsey) are downwards absolute to the Dodd-Jensen [](Core%20models.md). Hierarchy: - There are stationary many $Π_n$-Ramsey cardinals below each $Π_{n+1}$-Ramsey cardinal. - If $κ$ is $Π_{α+1}$-Ramsey and $α < κ^+$, then the set of $Π_α$-Ramsey cardinals less then $κ$ is in the $Π_{α+1}$-Ramsey filter on $κ$. Upper limit of consistency strength: - Any [measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinal is super completely Ramsey and a stationary limit of super completely Ramsey cardinals. Indescribability: - If $κ$ is $Π_n$-Ramsey, then $κ$ is $Π_{n+1}^1$-[indescribable](Indescribable.md "Indescribable"). If $X \subseteq κ$ is a $Π_n$-Ramsey subset, then $X$ is $Π_{n+1}^1$-indescribable. - For infinite $α$, if $κ$ is $Π_α$-Ramsey, then $κ$ is $Π^1_{2 ·(1+β)+ 1}$-indescribable for each $β < \min \{α, κ^+\}$ (Transfinite $Π^1_α$-indescribable is defined via finite games.).{% cite Sharpe2011 %} - If $κ$ is completely Ramsey, then $κ$ is $Π_1^2$-[indescribable](Indescribable.md "Indescribable").{% cite Holy2018 %} Equivalence: - A cardinal is completely Ramsey iff it is $ω$-very Ramsey. {% cite Sharpe2011 Nielsen2018 %} Relation with other variants of Ramseyness: - Strongly Ramsey cardinals are limits of completely Ramsey cardinals, but are not necessarily completely Ramsey themselves.{% cite Gitman2011a %} - Every $(ω+1)$-Ramsey cardinal is a completely Ramsey stationary limit of completely Ramsey cardinals.{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - Any $\Pi_2$-Ramsey cardinal is $α$-Mahlo–Ramsey for all $α < κ^+$. {% cite Sharpe2011 %} ## Almost Ramsey cardinal cf. (Vickers&Welch, 2001) An uncountable cardinal $\kappa$ is **almost Ramsey** if and only if $\kappa\rightarrow(\alpha)^{<\omega}$ for every $\alpha<\kappa$. Equivalently: - $\kappa\rightarrow(\alpha)^{<\omega}_\lambda$ for every $\alpha,\lambda<\kappa$ - For every structure $\mathcal{M}$ with language of size lt;\kappa$, there is are sets of indiscernibles $I\subseteq\kappa$ for $\mathcal{M}$ of any size lt;\kappa$. - For every $\alpha<\kappa$, $\eta_\alpha$ exists and $\eta_\alpha<\kappa$. - $\kappa=\text{sup}\{\eta_\alpha:\alpha<\kappa\}$ ($\eta_\alpha$ is the [$\alpha$-Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") cardinal.) Every almost Ramsey cardinal is a [](Beth.md), but the least almost Ramsey cardinal, if it exists, has cofinality $\omega$. In fact, the least almost Ramsey cardinal is not <a href="Weakly_inaccessible" class="mw-redirect" title="Weakly inaccessible">weakly inaccessible</a>, [worldly](Worldly.md "Worldly"), or <a href="Correct" class="mw-redirect" title="Correct">correct</a>. However, if the least almost Ramsey cardinal exists, it is larger than the least [$\omega_1$-Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") cardinal. Any regular almost Ramsey cardinal is worldly, and any worldly almost Ramsey cardinal $\kappa$ has $\kappa$ almost Ramsey cardinals below it. The existence of a worldly almost Ramsey cardinal is stronger than the existence of a proper class of almost Ramsey cardinals. Therefore, the existence of a Ramsey cardinal is stronger than the existence of a proper class of almost Ramsey cardinals. The existence of a proper class of almost Ramsey cardinals is equivalent to the existence of $\eta_\alpha$ for every $\alpha$. The existence of an almost Ramsey cardinal is stronger than the existence of an $\omega_1$-Erdős cardinal. The existence of an almost Ramsey cardinal is equivalent to the existence of $\eta^n(\omega)$ for every $n<\omega$. On one hand, if a almost Ramsey cardinal $\kappa$ exists, then $\omega<\kappa$. Then, $\eta_\omega$ is less than $\kappa$. Then, $\eta_{\eta_\omega}$ exists and is less than $\kappa$, and so on. On the other hand, if $\eta^n(\omega)$ exists for every $n<\omega$, then $\text{sup}\{\eta^n(\omega):n<\omega\}$ is almost Ramsey, and in fact the least almost Ramsey cardinal. Note that such a set exists by replacement and has a supremum by union. The Ramsey cardinals are precisely the [Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") almost Ramsey cardinals and also precisely the [[weakly compact]] almost Ramsey cardinals. If $κ$ is a $2$-weakly Erdős cardinal, then $κ$ is almost Ramsey.{% cite Sharpe2011 %} ## Strongly Ramsey cardinal Strongly Ramsey cardinals were introduced by Gitman in {% cite Gitman2011 %} (all information from there unless otherwise noted). They strengthen the $M$-ultrafilters characterization of Ramsey cardinals from weak $\kappa$-models to $\kappa$-models. A cardinal $\kappa$ is **strongly Ramsey** if every $A\subseteq\kappa$ is contained in a $\kappa$-model $M$ for which there exists a weakly amenable $M$-ultrafilter on $\kappa$. An $M$-ultrafilter for a $\kappa$-model $M$ is automatically countably complete since $\langle M,U\rangle$ satisfies that it is $\kappa$-complete and it must be correct about this since $M$ is closed under sequences of length less than $\kappa$. Properties: - Super Ramsey cardinals are strongly Ramsey limits of strongly Ramsey cardinals. - Strongly Ramsey cardinals are limits of completely Ramsey cardinals, but are not necessarily completely Ramsey themselves.{% cite Gitman2011a %} - Every strongly Ramsey cardinal is a stationary limit of almost fully Ramseys.{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - Strongly Ramsey cardinals are Ramsey and stationary limits of Ramsey cardinals. - The least strongly Ramsey cardinal is not [ineffable](Ineffable.md "Ineffable"). - Forcing related properties of strongly Ramsey cardinals are the same as those of Ramsey cardinals described above. {% cite Gitman %} - Strong Ramseyness is downward absolute to $K$. {% cite Gitman2011a %} ## Super Ramsey cardinal Super Ramsey cardinals were introduced by Gitman in {% cite Gitman2011 %} (all information from there unless otherwise noted). They strengthen one definition of strong Ramseyness. A weak $\kappa$-model $M$ is a $\kappa$-model if additionally $M^{\lt\kappa}\subseteq M$. A cardinal $\kappa$ is **super Ramsey** if and only if for every $A\subseteq\kappa$, there is some $\kappa$-model $M$ with $A\subseteq M\prec H_{\kappa^+}$ such that there is some $N$ and some $\kappa$-powerset preserving nontrivial elementary embedding $j:M\prec N$. The following are some facts about super Ramsey cardinals: - [Measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinals are super Ramsey limits of super Ramsey cardinals. - Fully Ramsey cardinals are super Ramsey limits of super Ramsey cardinals.{% cite Holy2018 %} - Super Ramsey cardinals are strongly Ramsey limits of strongly Ramsey cardinals. - Super Ramseyness is downward absolute to $K$. {% cite Gitman2011a %} - The required $M$ for a super Ramsey embedding is stationarily correct. ## $\alpha$-iterable cardinal The $\alpha$-iterable cardinals for $1\leq\alpha\leq\omega_1$ were introduced by Gitman in {% cite Gitman2011a %}. They form a hierarchy of large cardinal notions strengthening [[weakly compact]] cardinals, while weakening the $M$-ultrafilter characterization of Ramsey cardinals. Recall that if $\kappa$ is Ramsey, then every $A\subseteq\kappa$ is contained in a weak $\kappa$-model $M$ for which there exists an $M$-ultrafilter, the ultrapower construction with which may be iterated through all the ordinals. Suppose $M$ is a weak $\kappa$-model and $U$ is an $M$-ultrafilter on $\kappa$. Define that: - $U$ is $0$-good if the ultrapower is well-founded, - $U$ is 1-good if it is 0-good and weakly amenable, - for an ordinal $\alpha>1$, $U$ is $\alpha$-good, if it produces at least $\alpha$-many well-founded iterated ultrapowers. Using a theorem of Gaifman {% cite Gaifman1974 %}, if an $M$-ultrafilter is $\omega_1$-good, then it is already $\alpha$-good for every ordinal $\alpha$. For $1\leq\alpha\leq\omega_1$, a cardinal $\kappa$ is **$\alpha$-iterable** if every $A\subseteq\kappa$ is contained in a weak $\kappa$-model $M$ for which there exists an $\alpha$-good $M$-ultrafilter on $\kappa$. The $\alpha$-iterable cardinals form a hierarchy of strength above weakly compact cardinals and below Ramsey cardinals. The $1$-iterable cardinals are sometimes called the **weakly Ramsey** cardinals. ### Results Lower limit: - $1$-iterable cardinals are <a href="Weakly_ineffable" class="mw-redirect" title="Weakly ineffable">weakly ineffable</a> and stationary limits of <a href="Completely_ineffable" class="mw-redirect" title="Completely ineffable">completely ineffable</a> cardinals. The least $1$-iterable cardinal is not ineffable. {% cite Gitman2011 %} - Super weakly Ramsey cardinals are weakly Ramsey (=$1$-iterable) limits of weakly Ramsey cardinals. Upper limit: - A Ramsey cardinal is $\omega_1$-iterable and a stationary limit of $\omega_1$-iterable cardinals. This is already true of an $\omega_1$-[Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") cardinal. {% cite Sharpe2011 %} - If $C ∈ V\[H\]$, a forcing extension by $\mathrm{Coll}(ω, V_κ)$, is a club in $κ$ of generating indiscernibles for $V_κ$ of order-type $κ$ (like in the definition of <a href="Silver_cardinal" class="mw-redirect" title="Silver cardinal">Silver cardinals</a>), then each $ξ ∈ C$ is lt; ω_1$-iterable.{% cite Gitmana %} - $ω_1$-iterable cardinals are <a href="Strongly_unfoldable" class="mw-redirect" title="Strongly unfoldable">strongly unfoldable</a> in $L$.{% cite Gitman2011a %} Hierarchy: - An $\alpha$-iterable cardinal is $\beta$-iterable and a stationary limit of $\beta$-iterable cardinals for every $\beta<\alpha$. {% cite Gitman2011a %} - For $β > 0$, every $(α, β)$-Ramsey is a $β$-iterable stationary limit of $β$-iterables. - It is consistent from an $\omega$-[Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") cardinal that for every $n\in\omega$, there is a proper class of $n$-iterable cardinals. - For an additively indecomposable ordinal $λ ≤ ω_1$, $η_λ$ (the least $λ$-Erdős cardinal) is a limit of $λ$-iterable cardinals and if there is a $λ + 1$-iterable cardinal, then there is a $λ$-Erdős cardinal below it.{% cite Gitmana %} - A [](Huge.md) cardinal is an $n+1$-iterable limit of $n+1$-iterable cardinals. If $κ$ is $n+2$-iterable, then $V_κ$ is a model of proper class many virtually $n$-huge* cardinals.{% cite Gitmana %} - Every virtually rank-into-rank cardinal is an $ω$-<a href="Iterable" class="mw-redirect" title="Iterable">iterable</a> limit of $ω$-iterable cardinals.{% cite Gitmana %} Between $1$- and $2$-iterable: - A $2$-iterable cardinal implies the consistency of a [remarkable](Remarkable.md "Remarkable") cardinal: Every $2$-iterable cardinal is a limit of remarkable cardinals. {% cite Gitman2011a %} - Remarkable cardinals imply the consistency of $1$-iterable cardinals: If there is a remarkable cardinal, then there is a countable transitive model of ZFC with a proper class of $1$-iterable cardinals. {% cite Gitman2011a %} - If $κ$ is $2$-iterable, then $V_κ$ is a model of proper class many [](Extendible.md) cardinals for every $n < ω$, of proper class many <a href="Shelah" class="mw-redirect" title="Shelah">virtually Shelah for supercompactness</a> cardinals{% cite Gitmana %} and of proper class many <a href="Completely_remarkable" class="mw-redirect" title="Completely remarkable">completely remarkable</a> cardinals.{% cite Bagaria2017a %} - Virtually extendible cardinals are 1-iterable limits of 1-iterable cardinals.{% cite Gitmana %} Absoluteness: - $\omega_1$-iterable cardinals imply that <a href="Zero_sharp" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero sharp">$0^\sharplt;/a> exists and hence there cannot be $\omega_1$-iterable cardinals in $L$. For $L$-countable $\alpha$, the $\alpha$-iterable cardinals are downward absolute to $L$. In fact, if <a href="Zero_sharp" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero sharp">$0^\sharplt;/a> exists, then every Silver indiscernible is $\alpha$-iterable in $L$ for every $L$-countable $\alpha$. {% cite Gitman2011a %} - $\alpha$-iterable cardinals $\kappa$ are preserved by small forcing, by the canonical forcing of the ${\rm GCH}$, by fast function forcing, and by the forcing to add a slim $\kappa$-Kurepa tree. If $\kappa$ is $\alpha$-iterable, there is a forcing extension in which $\kappa$ remains $\alpha$-iterable and $2^\kappa\gt\kappa$. {% cite Gitman %} ## Mahlo–Ramsey cardinals The property of being Mahlo–Ramsey (MR) is a slight strengthening of Ramseyness introduced in analogy to [Mahlo](Mahlo.md "Mahlo") cardinals in {% cite Sharpe2011 %} (all information from there). For a regular cardinal $κ$ and a sequence of canonical functions $⟨ f_α : α < κ^+ ⟩$ - $κ$ is $0$-MR iff it is Ramsey. - $κ$ is $(α + 1 )$-MR iff for any $g : \mathcal{P}_{<ω}(κ) → 2$ there is an $X ∈ NS^+_κ$ such that $X$ is homogeneous for $g$ and $∀_{μ ∈ X} \text{$μ$ is $f_α (μ)$-MR}$. - $κ$ is $δ$-MR for limit $δ < κ^+$ iff it is $α$-MR for all $α < δ$. Any $\Pi_2$-Ramsey cardinal is $α$-MR for all $α < κ^+$. ## Very Ramsey cardinals For $X ⊆ κ$ and ordinal $α$, $G_R(X, α)$ is a certain game for two players with finitely many moves defined in (Sharpe&Welch11). $X$ is Sharpe-Welch $\alpha$-Ramsey iff (II) wins $G_R(X, α)$. $G_r(X, α)$ (also defined there) is a modification of the game allowing $1+α$ moves. $X$ is **$\alpha$-very Ramsey** iff (II) has a winning strategy in $G_r(X, α)$.{% cite Sharpe2011 %} For $n < ω$, the games $G_R(X, n)$ and $G_r(X, n)$ coincide.{% cite Sharpe2011 %} In analogy to coherent lt;α$-very Ramsey, one can define coherent lt;α$-very Ramsey cardinals. $α$-very Ramsey cardinals are equivalent to coherent lt;α$-very Ramsey cardinals for limit $α$ and to lt;(α+1)$-very Ramsey cardinals in general. (This just allows to “subtract one” for successor ordinals.){% cite Nielsen2018 %} Results: - A cardinal is completely Ramsey iff it is $ω$-very Ramsey. {% cite Sharpe2011 Nielsen2018 %} - If $κ$ is a [measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinal, then $κ$ is $κ$-very Ramsey.{% cite Sharpe2011 %} - If a cardinal is $ω_1$-very Ramsey (=strategic $ω_1$-Ramsey cardinal), then it is measurable in the [](Core%20models.md) unless <a href="Zero_pistol" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero pistol">$0^\Plt;/a> exists and an inner model with a [Woodin](Woodin.md "Woodin") cardinal exists. {% cite Sharpe2011 Nielsen2018 %} Additional results from {% cite Nielsen2018 %}: - For limit ordinal $α$, every coherent lt;ωα$-Ramsey is $ωα$-very Ramsey. - For any ordinal $α$, every coherent lt;α$-very Ramsey is coherent lt;α$-Ramsey. - For limit ordinal $α$, $κ$ is $ωα$-very Ramsey iff it is coherent lt;ωα$-Ramsey. - $κ$ is $λ$-very Ramsey iff it is strategic $λ$-Ramsey for any $λ$ with uncountable cofinality. ## Virtually Ramsey cardinal Virtually Ramsey cardinals were introduced by Sharpe and Welch in {% cite Sharpe2011 %}. They weaken the good indiscernibles characterization of Ramsey cardinals and were motivated by finding an upper bound on the consistency strength of a variant of Chang's Conjecture studied in {% cite Sharpe2011 %}. For $A\subseteq\kappa$, define that $\mathscr I=\{\alpha<\kappa\mid$ there is an unbounded good set of indiscernibles $I_\alpha\subseteq\alpha$ for $\langle L_\kappa\[A\],A\rangle\}$. A cardinal $\kappa$ is virtually Ramsey if for every $A\subseteq\kappa$, the set $\mathscr I$ contains a club of $\kappa$. Virtually Ramsey cardinals are [Mahlo](Mahlo.md "Mahlo") and a virtually Ramsey cardinal that is [[weakly compact]] is already Ramsey. If $κ$ is Ramsey, then there is a forcing extension destroying this, while preserving that $κ$ is virtually Ramsey. It is open whether virtually Ramsey cardinals are weaker than Ramsey cardinals. {% cite Gitman2011a Gitman %} If κ is virtually Ramsey then κ is [](Erdos.md).{% cite Sharpe2011 %} ## Super weakly Ramsey cardinal (All from {% cite Holy2018 %}) A cardinal $κ$ is **super weakly Ramsey** iff every $A ⊆ κ$ is contained, as an element, in a weak κ-[model](Model.md "Model") $M ≺ H(κ^+)$ for which there exists a $κ$-powerset preserving elementary embedding $j∶ M → N$. Strength: - Super weakly Ramsey cardinals are weakly Ramsey (=$1$-iterable) limits of weakly Ramsey cardinals. - Super weakly Ramsey cardinals are [ineffable](Ineffable.md "Ineffable"). - $ω$-Ramsey cardinals are super weakly Ramsey limits of super weakly Ramsey cardinals. ## $α$-Ramsey cardinal etc. ### $α$-Ramsey cardinal for cardinal $α$ (All from {% cite Holy2018 %}) For regular cardinal $α ≤ κ$, $κ$ is $α$-Ramsey iff for arbitrarily large regular cardinals $θ$, every $A ⊆ κ$ is contained, as an element, in some weak $κ$-model $M ≺ H(θ)$ which is closed under lt;α$-sequences, and for which there exists a $κ$-powerset preserving elementary embedding $j∶ M → N$. Note that, in the case $α = κ$, a weak $κ$-model closed under lt;κ$-sequences is exactly a $κ$-model. Alternate characterisation: - For regular uncountable cardinal $α ≤ κ$, $κ$ is $α$-Ramsey iff $κ = κ^{<κ}$ has the $α$-filter property. - $κ$ is $ω$-Ramsey iff $κ = κ^{<κ}$ has the well-founded $ω$-filter property. This characterisation works better for singular alpha $α$ (the original one would imply being $α^+$-Ramsey; well-founded $α$-filter property is better for countable cofinality). ### Games for definitions (from {% cite Nielsen2018 %} unless otherwise noted) For a weak $κ$-[model](Model.md "Model") $\mathcal{M}$, $μ$ is an *$\mathcal{M}$-<a href="Measure" class="mw-redirect" title="Measure">measure</a>* iff $(\mathcal{M}, \in, μ) \models \text{“$μ$ is a $κ$-complete ultrafilter on $κ$”}$. Games $G_1$ and $G_2$ are *equivalent* when each of two players has a winning strategy in $G_1$ if and only if he has one in $G_2$. The $α$-Ramsey cardinals are based upon *well-founded filter games*{% cite Holy2018 %} $wfG^θ_γ(κ)$ (full definition in sources). - Player I (*challenger*{% cite Holy2018 %}) gives $\subseteq$-increasing $κ$-models $\mathcal{M}_α ≺ H_θ$, - player II (*judge*{% cite Holy2018 %}) gives $\subseteq$-increasing filters $μ_α$ that are $\mathcal{M}_α$-measures - and II wins iff after $γ$ rounds $μ$ is an $\mathcal{M}$-normal good $\mathcal{M}$-measure for $μ = \bigcup_{α<γ} μ_α$ and $\mathcal{M} = \bigcup_{α<γ} \mathcal{M}_α$. The games $wfG^{θ_0}_γ(κ)$ and $wfG^{θ_1}_γ(κ)$ are equivalent for any $γ$ with $\mathrm{cof}(γ) \neq ω$ and any regular $θ_0, θ_1 < κ$. $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ, ζ)$ is a similar family of games (again full definition in sources). - Each of them lasts up to $γ+1$ rounds - and player II wins when he does not have to end the game before $γ+1$ rounds pass - (I gives $\subseteq$-increasing weak $κ$-models - and II must give normal $\mathcal{M}_α$-measures with additional requirements for limit $α$ (eg. $μ_α$ is $ζ$-good) and for the last move). For convenience - $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ) := \mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ, 0)$ - $\mathcal{G}_γ(κ) := \mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ)$ whenever $\mathrm{cof}(γ) \neq ω$ as again the existence of winning strategies in these games does not depend upon a specific $θ$. $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ)$, $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ, 1)$ and $wfG^θ_γ(κ)$ are all equivalent for all limit ordinals $γ \leq κ$. $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ, ζ)$ is equivalent to $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ)$ whenever $\mathrm{cof}(γ) > ω$. ### Generalisations (from {% cite Nielsen2018 %}) Now we can define $γ$-Ramsey cardinals for any ordinal $γ$ and other variants: Let $κ$ be a cardinal and $γ \leq κ$ an ordinal: - $κ$ is **$γ$-Ramsey** iff player I does not have a winning strategy in $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ)$ for all regular $θ > κ$. - $κ$ is **strategic $γ$-Ramsey** iff player II does have a winning strategy in $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ)$ for all regular $θ > κ$. - **(Strategic) genuine $γ$-Ramseys** and **(strategic) normal $γ$-Ramseys** are defined analogously, with the additional requirement for the last measure $μ_γ$ to be genuine and normal, respectively. - $κ$ is lt;γ$-Ramsey iff it is $α$-Ramsey for every $α < γ$. - $κ$ is **almost fully Ramsey** iff it is lt;κ$-Ramsey. - $κ$ is **fully Ramsey** iff it is $κ$-Ramsey. - $κ$ is **coherent lt;γ$-Ramsey** iff it is strategic lt;γ$-Ramsey and a single strategy works for player II in $\mathcal{G}_α(κ)$ for every $α < γ$. - I.e., in a choice of strategies for each $α$, strategies for greater $α$ contain strategies for lesser $α$. Full definition in {% cite Nielsen2018 %}. (Some of the notions defined in {% cite Nielsen2018 %} were not new, but gained more convenient names.) ### Filter property (from {% cite Holy2018 %}) $κ$ has the **filter property** iff for every subset $X$ of $\mathcal{P}(κ)$ of size $≤κ$, there is a lt;κ$-complete filter $F$ on $κ$ which measures $X$. For normal filter we talk about *normal filter property*. Strengthenings: - $κ$ has the **$γ$-filter property** iff player I does not have a winning strategy in $G^θ_γ(κ)$. - $κ$ has the **strategic $γ$-filter property** iff player II does have a winning strategy in $G^θ_γ(κ)$. - $κ$ has the **well-founded $(γ, θ)$-filter property** iff player I does not have a winning strategy in $wfG^θ_γ(κ)$. - $κ$ has the **well-founded $γ$-filter property** iff it has the well-founded $(γ, θ)$-filter property for all regular $θ > κ$. For $γ_1 > γ_0$, the $γ_1$-filter property implies the $γ_0$-filter property. ### Results Results in the finite case (for $n < ω$):{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - For a cardinal $κ=κ^{<κ}$ - $κ$ is [[weakly compact]] iff it is 0-Ramsey; - $κ$ is <a href="Weakly_ineffable" class="mw-redirect" title="Weakly ineffable">weakly ineffable</a> iff it is genuine 0-Ramsey; - $κ$ is [ineffable](Ineffable.md "Ineffable") iff it is normal 0-Ramsey. (An uncountable cardinal κ has the normal filter property iff it is ineffable.{% cite Holy2018 %}) - Every $n$-Ramsey $κ$ is $Π^1_{2 n+1}$-indescribable. This is optimal, as $n$-Ramseyness can be described by a $Π^1_{2 n+2}$-formula. - Every lt;ω$-Ramsey cardinal is $∆^2_0$-indescribable. - Every normal $n$-Ramsey $κ$ is $Π^1_{2 n+2}$-indescribable. This is optimal, as normal $n$-Ramseyness can be described by a $Π^1_{2 n+3}$-formula. - Every $n+1$-Ramsey is a normal $n$-Ramsey stationary limit of normal $n$-Ramseys and every normal $n$-Ramsey is an $n$-Ramsey stationary limit of $n$-Ramseys. - Genuine- and normal $n$-Ramseys are downwards absolute to $L$. - Every $(n+1)$-Ramsey is normal $n$-Ramsey in $L$. Therefore, lt;ω$-Ramseys are downwards absolute to $L$. Results for $ω$-Ramsey:{% cite Holy2018 %} - $ω$-Ramsey cardinals are super weakly Ramsey limits of super weakly Ramsey cardinals. - $ω$-Ramsey cardinals are limits of cardinals with the $ω$-filter property (=completely [ineffable](Ineffable.md "Ineffable"){% cite Nielsen2018 %}). - $ω$-Ramsey cardinals are downwards absolute to $L$. If <a href="Zero_sharp" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero sharp">$0^♯lt;/a> exists, then all Silver indiscernibles are $ω$-Ramsey in $L$. Results for strategic $ω$-Ramsey:{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - <a href="Virtually_measurable" class="mw-redirect" title="Virtually measurable">Virtually measurable</a> cardinals, strategic $ω$-Ramsey cardinals and [remarkable](Remarkable.md "Remarkable") cardinals are equiconsistent. - Every virtually measurable cardinal is strategic $ω$-Ramsey, and every strategic $ω$-Ramsey cardinal is virtually measurable in $L$. - If $κ$ is virtually measurable, then either $κ$ is [remarkable](Remarkable.md "Remarkable") in $L$ or $L_κ \models \text{“there is a proper class of virtually measurables”}$. - Remarkable cardinals are strategic $ω$-Ramsey limits of $ω$-Ramsey cardinals. - Therefore, if $κ$ is a strategic ω-Ramsey cardinal then $L_κ \models \text{“there is a proper class of $ω$-Ramseys”}$. Equiconsistency with the [measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinal: - The existence of a strategic $(ω+1)$-Ramsey cardinal (and of strategic fully Ramsey cardinal) is equiconsistent with the existence of a measurable cardinal.{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - If $κ$ is a measurable cardinal, then $κ$ is $κ$-very Ramsey. If a cardinal is $ω_1$-very Ramsey (=strategic $ω_1$-Ramsey cardinal), then it is measurable in the [](Core%20models.md) unless <a href="Zero_pistol" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero pistol">$0^\Plt;/a> exists and an inner model with a [Woodin](Woodin.md "Woodin") cardinal exists. {% cite Sharpe2011 Nielsen2018 %} - If $κ$ is uncountable, $κ = κ^{<κ}$ and $2^κ = κ^+$, then the following are equivalent:{% cite Holy2018 %} - $κ$ is measurable. - $κ$ satisfies the $κ^+$-filter property. - $κ$ satisfies the strategic $κ^+$-filter property. - On the other hand, starting from a $κ^{++}$-tall cardinal $κ$, it is consistent that there is a cardinal $κ$ with the strategic $κ^+$-filter property, however $κ$ is not measurable. Being downwards absolute to the [](Core%20models.md):{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - If <a href="Zero_pistol" class="mw-redirect" title="Zero pistol">$0^\Plt;/a> does not exist: - If $α$ is a limit ordinal with uncountable cofinality, then being $α$-Ramsey is downwards absolute to $\mathbf{K}$. - If $α$ is a limit ordinal, then genuine $α$-Ramseyness and normal $α$-Ramseyness are both downwards absolute to $\mathbf{K}$. - if $α$ is a limit of limit ordinals, then lt;α$-Ramseyness is downwards absolute to $\mathbf{K}$. Strategic $α$-Ramsey (including coherent lt;α$-Ramsey) and $α$-very Ramsey:{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - For limit ordinal $α$, every coherent lt;ωα$-Ramsey is $ωα$-very Ramsey. - For any ordinal $α$, every coherent lt;α$-very Ramsey is coherent lt;α$-Ramsey. - For limit ordinal $α$, $κ$ is $ωα$-very Ramsey iff it is coherent lt;ωα$-Ramsey. - $κ$ is $λ$-very Ramsey iff it is strategic $λ$-Ramsey for any $λ$ with uncountable cofinality. Hierarchy:{% cite Holy2018 %} - If $ω ≤ α_0 < α_1 ≤ κ$, both $α_0$ and $α_1$ are cardinals, and $κ$ is $α_1$-Ramsey, then there is a proper class of $α_0$-Ramsey cardinals in $V_κ$. If $α_0$ is regular, then $κ$ is a limit of $α_0$-Ramsey cardinals. - If $α ≤ κ$ are both cardinals and $κ$ is $α$-Ramsey, then $κ$ has a well-founded $α$-filter sequence. - If $ω ≤ α < β ≤ κ$ are cardinals and $κ$ has a $β$-filter sequence, then there is a proper class of $α$-Ramsey cardinals in $V_κ$. If $α$ is regular, then $κ$ is a limit of $α$-Ramsey cardinals. Other: - Every $(ω+1)$-Ramsey cardinal is a completely Ramsey stationary limit of completely Ramsey cardinals.{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - Every strongly Ramsey cardinal is a stationary limit of almost fully Ramseys.{% cite Nielsen2018 %} - Fully Ramsey cardinals are super Ramsey limits of super Ramsey cardinals.{% cite Holy2018 %} - [Measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinals are limits of fully Ramsey cardinals.{% cite Holy2018 %} ### $(α, β)$-Ramsey cardinals (All information from {% cite Nielsen2018 %}) $κ$ is **$(α, β)$-Ramsey** iff player I has no winning strategy in $\mathcal{G}^θ_α(κ, β)$ for all regular $θ > κ$. Of course, this notion is interesting only for $\mathrm{cof}(α) = ω$. $α$-Ramsey cardinals are by definition equivalent to $(α, 0)$-Ramsey cardinals. Position in the hierarchy of [Erdős](Erdos.md "Erdos") and iterable cardinals: - For $β > 0$, every $(α, β)$-Ramsey is a $β$-iterable stationary limit of $β$-iterables. - For additively closed $ω \leq α \leq ω_1$, any $α$-Erdős cardinal is a limit of $(ω, α)$-Ramsey cardinals. This means also that $(ω, α)$-Ramsey cardinals are consistent with $V = L$ if $α < ω_1^L$ and that they are not if $α = ω_1$ . ### $(γ, θ)$-Ramsey cardinals $κ$ is **$(γ, θ)$-Ramsey** iff player I has no winning strategy in $\mathcal{G}^θ_γ(κ)$ (i.e. $κ$ is $γ$-Ramsey iff it is $(γ, θ)$-Ramsey for every $θ > κ$). Not much is known about them in general.{% cite Nielsen2018 %} ## M-rank (from {% cite Carmody2016 %}) M-rank for Ramsey and Ramsey-like cardinals is analogous to [](Mitchell%20rank%20and%20Mitchell%20order.md). A difference is that M-rank for Ramsey-like cardinals can be at most $\kappa^+$ (because an ultrapower of a weak $κ$-model has size at most $κ$) and Mitchell rank for [measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") cardinals can be at most $(2^\kappa)^+$. Definition of the M-order: For $κ$ having a large-cardinal property $\mathscr{P}$ with an embedding characterisation and for two witness collections $\mathcal{U}$ and $\mathcal{W}$ of $\mathscr{P}$-measures, we say that $U⊳W$ if - for every $W∈\mathcal{W}$ and $A⊆κ$ in the ultrapower $N_W$ of $M_W$ by $W$, there is an $A$-good $U∈ \mathcal{U} ∩ N_W$ such that $N_W \models \text{“$\mathcal{U}$ is an $A$-good $\mathscr{P}$-measure on $κ$”}$. - $\mathcal{U} ⊆ ⋃_{W∈\mathcal{W}} N_W$. Results: - Any strongly Ramsey cardinal $κ$ has Ramsey M-rank $κ^+$, - any super Ramsey cardinal $κ$ has strongly Ramsey M-rank $κ^+$ - and any measurable cardinal $κ$ has super Ramsey M-rank $κ^+$. Ramsey and Ramsey-like M-orders can be softly killed (Rank $α$ can be turned into rank $β$ for any $β < α$) using cofinality-preserving forcing extension.