
Here in the playroom, you will find a variety of stimulating
entertainments.
## Hilbert's Grand Hotel
## Diary of Tristram Shandy
## On the number of possible finite books
Let us define, in precise mathematical style, that a *book* is a finite
sequence of pages, the first containing the title of the book and the
author's name, and the subsequent pages each containing a finite
sequence of text, written in a normal size with a normal font, with
margins at the side and a page number at the bottom. Let us suppose
there is no funny business with these books, with increasingly small
text, for example: each page consists of at most 50 lines, with each
line consisting of at most 100 characters (from the ASCII character set,
say), and there are margins at all four sides and the page numbers,
written in the usual decimal manner, start at 1 and increment by 1 with
each page. In short, a normal book.
How many books are there? It may seem at first that there should be
infinitely many possible books, since we would have the book consisting
entirely of the letter A, repeated endlessly to any desired length, and
the book with B, and so on, of any desired length.
But further thought will reveal that that in fact, there are only
finitely many possible books. The reason is that it is not actually
possible to have arbitrarily long books that obey the requirements set
out. This is because once the book becomes very long, the page numbers
become larger and larger, using up more and more of the available space,
just for the page number. Eventually, the entire page is filled just
with the page number, with no room for additional text. Indeed,
eventually, the page number is too large to fit, and the book must end.
So there is a finite bound of the length of a book, and thus only
finitely many books altogether.
## Supertasks
A *supertask* is a task involving infinitely many steps, and many of the
other entries on this page can be classified as supertasks.
## Zeno's paradox
Perhaps Zeno of Elea (ca. 450 B.C.) was the first to grapple with the
supertask concept in his famous paradoxical argument, now known as
Zeno's paradox, that it is impossible to go from here to there. Before
arriving, one must first get halfway there, and before that one must get
halfway to the halfway point, and so on, ad infinitum. Because one
cannot accomplish these infinitely many tasks, Zeno argued, all motion
is impossible. Thus, he takes the impossibility of completing a
supertask as the foundation of his reductio.
## Thomson's lamp
In the twentieth century philosophical literature, the puzzles and
paradoxes continue. Take Thomson's lamp (Thomson 1954), for example,
which is on for $1/2$ minute, off for $1/4$ minute, on for $1/8$ minute,
and so on. After one minute (the sum of the series
$1/2+1/4+1/8+\cdots$), is it on or off? The literature is full of
answers. Another toy example is the super-$\pi$ machine, which writes
out the successive digits of $\pi$ on a tape, the first in $1/2$
minute, the next in $1/4$ minute, and so on, so that all the digits are
written in a finite amount of time. Because there can be no last or
final step in such a process, Chihara (1965) has criticized the
completion of such an algorithm as unintelligible.
## Deal with the devil
In a more entertaining example, let's suppose that you have infinitely
many one dollar bills (numbered 1, 3, 5, $\ldots$) and upon entering a
nefarious underground bar, you come upon the Devil sitting at a table
piled high with money. You sit down, and the Devil explains to you that
he has an attachment to your particular bills and is willing to pay you
a premium to buy them from you. Specifically, he is willing to pay two
dollars for each of your one-dollar bills. To carry out the exchange, he
proposes an infinite series of transactions, in each of which he will
hand over to you two dollars and take from you one dollar. The first
transaction will take $1/2$ hour, the second $1/4$ hour, the third $1/8$
hour, and so on, so that after one hour the entire exchange will be
complete. The Devil takes a sip of whiskey while you mull it over;
should you accept his proposal? Perhaps you think you will become
richer, or perhaps you think with infinitely many bills it will make no
difference? At the very least, you think, it will do no harm, and so the
contract is signed and the procedure begins. How could the deal harm
you?
It appears initially that you have made a good bargain, because at every
step of the transaction, he pays you two dollars and you give up only
one. The Devil is very particular, however, about the order in which the
bills are exchanged. The contract stipulates that in each
sub-transaction he buys from you your lowest-numbered bill and pays you
with higher-numbered bills. Thus, on the first transaction he accepts
from you bill number 1, and pays you with bills numbered 2 and 4. On the
next transaction he buys from you bill number 2 (which he had just paid
you) and gives you bills numbered 6 and 8. Next, he buys bill number 3
from you with bills 10 and 12, and so on. When all the exchanges are
completed, what do you discover? You have no money left at all! The
reason is that at the $n^{\rm th}$ exchange, the Devil took from you
bill number $n$, and never subsequently returned it to you. So while it
seemed as though you were becoming no poorer with each exchange, in fact
the final destination of every dollar bill in the transaction is under
the Devil's ownership. The Devil is a shrewd banker, and you should have
paid more attention to the details of the supertask transaction to which
you agreed. And similarly, the point is that when we design supertask
algorithms to solve mathematical questions, we must take care not to
make inadvertent assumptions about what may be true only for finite
algorithms.
## Supertasks in physics
Supertasks have also been studied by the physicists. In classical
mechanics under the Newtonian gravity law (neglecting relativity), it is
possible to arrange finitely many stars in orbiting pairs, each pair
orbiting the common center of mass of all the pairs, and a single tiny
moon racing faster around, squeezing just so between the dual stars so
as to pick up speed with every such transaction. Assuming point masses
(or collapsing stars to avoid collision), the arrangement can be made to
lead by Newton's law of gravitation to infinitely many revolutions in
finite time.
Other supertasks reveal apparent violations of the conservation of
energy in Newtonian physics: imagine infinitely many billiard balls of
successively diminishing size, converging to a point (see Laraudogoitia
1996). The balls are initially at rest, but then the first is set
rolling. It collides with the next, transferring all its energy, and
that ball begins to roll. Each ball in turn collides with the next,
transferring all its energy. Because of the physical arrangements of the
system, the motion disappears in a sense into the singularity; after a
finite amount of time all the collisions have taken place, and the balls
are at rest. So we have described a physical process in which energy is
conserved at each step, in every interaction, but not overall through
time.
Another arrangement has the balls spaced further and further out to
infinity, pushing the singularity out to the point at infinity. The
first ball knocks the second, which sends the next flying, and so on out
to infinity. If the balls speed up sufficiently fast, under Newtonian
rules it can be arranged that all the motion is completed in a finite
amount of time. The interesting thing about this example and the
previous one is that time-symmetry allows them to run in reverse, with
static configurations of balls suddenly coming into motion without
violating conservation of energy in any interaction.
More computationally significant supertasks have been proposed by
physicists in the context of relativity theory (Pitowsky 1990, Earman
1995, Earman, et. al. 1993, Hogarth 1992, Hogarth 1994). Suppose that
you want to know the answer to some number theoretic conjecture, such as
whether there are additional Fermat primes (primes of the form $2^{2^n}
+ 1$), a conjecture that can be confirmed with a single numerical
example. The way to solve the problem is to board a rocket, while
setting your graduate students to work on earth looking for an example.
While you fly faster and faster around the earth, your graduate
students, and their graduate students and so on, continue the exhaustive
search, with the agreement that if they ever find an example, they will
send a radio signal up to the rocket. Meanwhile, by accelerating
sufficiently fast towards the speed of light (but never exceeding it),
it is possible to arrange that the relativistic time contraction on the
rocket will mean that a finite amount of time on the rocket corresponds
to an infinite amount of time on the earth. The point is therefore that
by means of the communication between the two reference frames, what
corresponds to an infinite search can be completed in a finite amount of
time.
With more complicated arrangements of rockets flying around rockets, one
can solve more complicated number theoretic questions. Hogarth (1994)
has explained how to determine in this way the truth of any arithmetic
statement. More unusual relativistic Malament-Hogarth spacetimes can be
(mathematically) constructed to avoid the unpleasantness of unbounded
acceleration required in these rocket examples (see also Hogarth 1992,
Pitowsky 1990).
These computational examples speak to a widely held strengthening of
Church's thesis, namely, the view that the classical theory of
computability has correctly captured the notion of what it means to be
effectively computable. Because the relativistic rocket examples provide
algorithms for computing functions, such as the halting problem, that
are not computable by Turing machines, one can view them as refuting
this thesis. Supporters of this view emphasize that when thinking about
what is in principle computable, we must attend to the computational
power available to us as a consequence of the fact that we live in a
relativistic or quantum-mechanical universe. To ignore this power is to
pretend that we live in a Newtonian world.
## Library of Babel
\[libraryofbabel.info\]
## Ross-Littlewood paradox
## Metagame
Several of the sections above contained material from
{% cite Hamkins2002 %}.