**Huge** cardinals (and their variants) were introduced by Kenneth Kunen in 1972 as a very large cardinal axiom. Kenneth Kunen first used them to prove that the consistency of the existence of a huge cardinal implies the consistency of $\text{ZFC}$+"there is a $\omega_2$-saturated $\sigma$-[ideal](Filter.md "Filter") on $\omega_1quot;. It is now known that only a [Woodin](Woodin.md "Woodin") cardinal is needed for this result. However, the consistency of the existence of an $\omega_2$-complete $\omega_3$-saturated $\sigma$-ideal on $\omega_2$, as far as the set theory world is concerned, still requires an almost huge cardinal. {% cite Kanamori2009 %} ## Definitions Their formulation is similar to that of the formulation of [superstrong](Superstrong.md "Superstrong") cardinals. A huge cardinal is to a [supercompact](Supercompact.md "Supercompact") cardinal as a superstrong cardinal is to a [strong](Strong.md "Strong") cardinal, more precisely. The definition is part of a generalized phenomenon known as the "double helix", in which for some large cardinal properties n-$P_0$ and n-$P_1$, n-$P_0$ has less consistency strength than n-$P_1$, which has less consistency strength than (n+1)-$P_0$, and so on. This phenomenon is seen only around the [](N-fold_variants.md) as of modern set theoretic concerns. {% cite Kentaro2007 %} Although they are very large, there is a first-order definition which is equivalent to n-hugeness, so the $\theta$-th n-huge cardinal is first-order definable whenever $\theta$ is first-order definable. This definition can be seen as a (very strong) strengthening of the first-order definition of [measurability](Measurable.md "Measurable"). ### Elementary embedding definitions The elementary embedding definitions are somewhat standard. Let $j:V\rightarrow M$ be a nontrivial [](Elementary%20embedding.md) of $V$ into a [transitive](Transitive.md "Transitive") class $M$ with critical point $\kappa$. Then: - $\kappa$ is **almost n-huge with target $\lambda$** iff $\lambda=j^n(\kappa)$ and $M$ is closed under all of its sequences of length less than $\lambda$ (that is, $M^{<\lambda}\subseteq M$). - $\kappa$ is **n-huge with target $\lambda$** iff $\lambda=j^n(\kappa)$ and $M$ is closed under all of its sequences of length $\lambda$ ($M^\lambda\subseteq M$). - $\kappa$ is **almost n-huge** iff it is almost n-huge with target $\lambda$ for some $\lambda$. - $\kappa$ is **n-huge** iff it is n-huge with target $\lambda$ for some $\lambda$. - $\kappa$ is **super almost n-huge** iff for every $\gamma$, there is some $\lambda>\gamma$ for which $\kappa$ is almost n-huge with target $\lambda$ (that is, the target can be made arbitrarily large). - $\kappa$ is **super n-huge** iff for every $\gamma$, there is some $\lambda>\gamma$ for which $\kappa$ is n-huge with target $\lambda$. - $\kappa$ is **almost huge**, **huge**, **super almost huge**, and **superhuge** iff it is **almost 1-huge**, **1-huge**, etc. respectively. ### Ultrahuge cardinals A cardinal $\kappa$ is **$\lambda$-ultrahuge** for $\lambda>\kappa$ if there exists a nontrivial elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ for some transitive class $M$ such that $j(\kappa)>\lambda$, $M^{j(\kappa)}\subseteq M$ and $V_{j(\lambda)}\subseteq M$. A cardinal is **ultrahuge** if it is $\lambda$-ultrahuge for all $\lambda\geq\kappa$. <a href="http://logicatorino.altervista.org/slides/150619tsaprounis.pdf" class="external autonumber">[1]</a> Notice how similar this definition is to the alternative characterization of [extendible](Extendible.md "Extendible") cardinals. Furthermore, this definition can be extended in the obvious way to define $\lambda$-ultra n-hugeness and ultra n-hugeness, as well as the "*almost*" variants. ### Hyperhuge cardinals A cardinal $\kappa$ is **$\lambda$-hyperhuge** for $\lambda>\kappa$ if there exists a nontrivial elementary embedding $j:V\to M$ for some inner model $M$ such that $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \kappa$, $j(\kappa)>\lambda$ and $^{j(\lambda)}M\subseteq M$. A cardinal is **hyperhuge** if it is $\lambda$-hyperhuge for all $\lambda>\kappa$. {% cite Usuba2017 Boney2017 %} ### Huge* cardinals A cardinal $κ$ is **$n$-huge*** if for some $α > κ$, $\kappa$ is the critical point of an elementary embedding $j : V_α → V_β$ such that $j^n (κ) < α$.{% cite Gitmana %} Hugeness* variant is formulated in a way allowing for a virtual variant consistent with $V=L$: A cardinal $κ$ is **virtually $n$-huge*** if for some $α > κ$, in a set-forcing extension, $\kappa$ is the critical point of an elementary embedding $j : V_α → V_β$ such that $j^n(κ) < α$.{% cite Gitmana %} ### Ultrafilter definition The first-order definition of n-huge is somewhat similar to [measurability](Measurable.md "Measurable"). Specifically, $\kappa$ is measurable iff there is a nonprincipal $\kappa$-complete [ultrafilter](Filter.md "Filter"), $U$, over $\kappa$. A cardinal $\kappa$ is n-huge with target $\lambda$ iff there is a normal $\kappa$-complete ultrafilter, $U$, over $\mathcal{P}(\lambda)$, and cardinals $\kappa=\lambda_0<\lambda_1<\lambda_2...<\lambda_{n-1}<\lambda_n=\lambda$ such that: $\forall i<n(\{x\subseteq\lambda:\text{order-type}(x\cap\lambda_{i+1})=\lambda_i\}\in U)$ Where $\text{order-type}(X)$ is the [order-type](Order-isomorphism.md "Order-isomorphism") of the poset $(X,\in)$. {% cite Kanamori2009 %} $\kappa$ is then super n-huge if for all ordinals $\theta$ there is a $\lambda>\theta$ such that $\kappa$ is n-huge with target $\lambda$, i.e. $\lambda_n$ can be made arbitrarily large. If $j:V\to M$ is such that $M^{j^n(\kappa)}\subseteq M$ (i.e. $j$ witnesses n-hugeness) then there is a ultrafilter $U$ as above such that, for all $k\leq n$, $\lambda_k = j^k(\kappa)$, i.e. it is not only $\lambda=\lambda_n$ that is an iterate of $\kappa$ by $j$; all members of the $\lambda_k$ sequence are. As an example, $\kappa$ is 1-huge with target $\lambda$ iff there is a normal $\kappa$-complete ultrafilter, $U$, over $\mathcal{P}(\lambda)$ such that $\{x\subseteq\lambda:\text{order-type}(x)=\kappa\}\in U$. The reason why this would be so surprising is that every set $x\subseteq\lambda$ with every set of order-type $\kappa$ would be in the ultrafilter; that is, every set containing $\{x\subseteq\lambda:\text{order-type}(x)=\kappa\}$ as a subset is considered a "large set." As for hyperhugeness, the following are equivalent:{% cite Boney2017 %} - $κ$ is $λ$-hyperhuge; - $μ > λ$ and a normal, fine, κ-complete ultrafilter exists on $\[μ\]^λ_{∗κ} := \{s ⊂ μ : \|s\| = λ, \|s ∩ κ\| ∈ κ, \mathrm{otp}(s ∩ λ) < κ\}$; - $\mathbb{L}_{κ,κ}$ is $\[μ\]^λ_{∗κ}$-$κ$-compact for type omission. ### Coherent sequence characterization of almost hugeness ### $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge cardinals (this section from {% cite Bagaria2012 %}) $κ$ is **<a href="Correct" class="mw-redirect" title="Correct">$C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge</a>** iff it is $m$-huge and $j(κ) ∈ C^{(n)}$ ($C^{(n)}$-huge if it is huge and $j(κ) ∈ C^{(n)}$). Equivalent definition in terms of normal measures: κ is $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge iff it is uncountable and there is a $κ$-complete normal <a href="Ultrafilter" class="mw-redirect" title="Ultrafilter">ultrafilter</a> $U$ over some $P(λ)$ and cardinals $κ = λ_0 < λ_1 < . . . < λ_m = λ$, with $λ_1 ∈ C (n)$ and such that for each $i < m$, $\{x ∈ P(λ) : ot(x ∩ λ i+1 ) = λ i \} ∈ U$. It follows that “$κ$ is $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge” is $Σ_{n+1}$ expressible. Every huge cardinal is $C^{(1)}$-huge. The first $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge cardinal is not $C^{(n+1)}$-$m$-huge, for all $m$ and $n$ greater or equal than $1$. For suppose $κ$ is the least $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge cardinal and $j : V → M$ witnesses that $κ$ is $C^{(n+1)}$-$m$-huge. Then since “x is $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge” is $Σ_{n+1}$ expressible, we have $V_{j(κ)} \models$ “$κ$ is $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge”. Hence, since $(V_{j(κ)})^M = V_{j(κ)}$, $M \models$ “$∃_{δ < j(κ)}(V_{j(κ)} \models$ “δ is huge”$)$”. By elementarity, there is a $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge cardinal less than $κ$ in $V$ – contradiction. Assuming [](Rank_into_rank.md), if $δ$ is a limit cardinal (instead of a successor of a limit cardinal – Kunen’s Theorem excludes other cases), it is equal to $sup\{j^m(κ) : m ∈ ω\}$ where $j$ is the elementary embedding. Then $κ$ and $j^m(κ)$ are $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge (inter alia) in $V_δ$, for all $n$ and $m$. If $κ$ is $C^{(n)}$-$\mathrm{I3}$, then it is $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge, for all $m$, and there is a normal ultrafilter $\mathcal{U}$ over $κ$ such that $\{α < κ : α$ is $C^{(n)}$-$m$-huge for every $m\} ∈ \mathcal{U}$. ## Consistency strength and size Hugeness exhibits a phenomenon associated with similarly defined large cardinals (the [](N-fold_variants.md)) known as the *double helix*. This phenomenon is when for one n-fold variant, letting a cardinal be called n-$P_0$ iff it has the property, and another variant, n-$P_1$, n-$P_0$ is weaker than n-$P_1$, which is weaker than (n+1)-$P_0$. {% cite Kentaro2007 %} In the consistency strength hierarchy, here is where these lay (top being weakest): - [measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") = 0-[superstrong](Superstrong.md "Superstrong") = 0-huge - n-superstrong - n-fold supercompact - (n+1)-fold strong, n-fold extendible - (n+1)-fold Woodin, n-fold Vopěnka - (n+1)-fold Shelah - almost n-huge - super almost n-huge - n-huge - super n-huge - ultra n-huge - (n+1)-superstrong All huge variants lay at the top of the double helix restricted to some [](Omega.md) n, although each are bested by <a href="Rank-into-rank" class="mw-redirect" title="Rank-into-rank">I3</a> cardinals (the [](Elementary%20embedding.md) of the I3 elementary embeddings). In fact, every I3 is preceeded by a stationary set of n-huge cardinals, for all n. {% cite Kanamori2009 %} Similarly, every huge cardinal $\kappa$ is almost huge, and there is a normal measure over $\kappa$ which contains every almost huge cardinal $\lambda<\kappa$. Every superhuge cardinal $\kappa$ is [extendible](Extendible.md "Extendible") and there is a normal measure over $\kappa$ which contains every extendible cardinal $\lambda<\kappa$. Every (n+1)-huge cardinal $\kappa$ has a normal measure which contains every cardinal $\lambda$ such that $V_\kappa\modelsquot;$\lambda$ is super n-huge" {% cite Kanamori2009 %}, in fact it contains every cardinal $\lambda$ such that $V_\kappa\modelsquot;$\lambda$ is ultra n-huge". Every n-huge cardinal is m-huge for every m<n. Similarly with almost n-hugeness, super n-hugeness, and super almost n-hugeness. Every almost huge cardinal is [Vopěnka](Vopenka.md "Vopenka") (therefore the consistency of the existence of an almost-huge cardinal implies the consistency of Vopěnka's principle). {% cite Kanamori2009 %} Every ultra n-huge is super n-huge and a stationary limit of super n-huge cardinals. Every super almost (n+1)-huge is ultra n-huge and a stationary limit of ultra n-huge cardinals. In terms of size, however, the least n-huge cardinal is smaller than the least [supercompact](Supercompact.md "Supercompact") cardinal (assuming both exist). {% cite Kanamori2009 %} This is because n-huge cardinals have upward reflection properties, while supercompacts have downward reflection properties. Thus for any $\kappa$ which is supercompact and has an n-huge cardinal above it, $\kappa$ "reflects downward" that n-huge cardinal: there are $\kappa$-many n-huge cardinals below $\kappa$. On the other hand, the least super n-huge cardinals have *both* upward and downward reflection properties, and are all *much* larger than the least supercompact cardinal. It is notable that, while almost 2-huge cardinals have higher consistency strength than superhuge cardinals, the least almost 2-huge is much smaller than the least super almost huge. While not every $n$-huge cardinal is [strong](Strong.md "Strong"), if $\kappa$ is almost $n$-huge with targets $\lambda_1,\lambda_2...\lambda_n$, then $\kappa$ is $\lambda_n$-strong as witnessed by the generated $j:V\prec M$. This is because $j^n(\kappa)=\lambda_n$ is [measurable](Measurable.md "Measurable") and therefore $\beth_{\lambda_n}=\lambda_n$ and so $V_{\lambda_n}=H_{\lambda_n}$ and because $M^{<\lambda_n}\subset M$, $H_\theta\subset M$ for each $\theta<\lambda_n$ and so $\cup\{H_\theta:\theta<\lambda_n\} = \cup\{V_\theta:\theta<\lambda_n\} = V_{\lambda_n}\subset M$. Every almost $n$-huge cardinal with targets $\lambda_1,\lambda_2...\lambda_n$ is also [$\theta$-supercompact](Supercompact.md "Supercompact") for each $\theta<\lambda_n$, and every $n$-huge cardinal with targets $\lambda_1,\lambda_2...\lambda_n$ is also $\lambda_n$-supercompact. For $2$-huge $κ$, $V_κ$ is a model of $\mathrm{ZFC}$+“there are proper class many hyper-huge cardinals”.{% cite Usuba2017 %} Hyper-huge cardinals are extendible limits of extendible cardinals.{% cite Usuba2019 %} An $n$-huge* cardinal is an $n$-huge limit of $n$-huge cardinals. Every $n + 1$-huge cardinal is $n$-huge*.{% cite Gitmana %} As for virtually $n$-huge*:{% cite Gitmana %} - If $κ$ is virtually huge*, then $V_κ$ is a model of proper class many [](Extendible.md) cardinals. - A virtually $n+1$-huge* cardinal is a limit of virtually $n$-huge* cardinals. - A virtually $n$-huge* cardinal is an $n+1$-<a href="Iterable" class="mw-redirect" title="Iterable">iterable</a> limit of $n+1$-iterable cardinals. If $κ$ is $n+2$-iterable, then $V_κ$ is a model of proper class many virtually $n$-huge* cardinals. - Every <a href="Rank-into-rank" class="mw-redirect" title="Rank-into-rank">virtually rank-into-rank</a> cardinal is a virtually $n$-huge* limit of virtually $n$-huge* cardinals for every $n < ω$. ### The $\omega$-huge cardinals A cardinal $\kappa$ is **almost $\omega$-huge** iff there is some transitive model $M$ and an elementary embedding $j:V\prec M$ with critical point $\kappa$ such that $M^{<\lambda}\subset M$ where $\lambda$ is the smallest cardinal above $\kappa$ such that $j(\lambda)=\lambda$. Similarly, $\kappa$ is **$\omega$-huge** iff the model $M$ can be required to have $M^\lambda\subset M$. Sadly, $\omega$-huge cardinals are inconsistent with ZFC by a version of Kunen's inconsistency theorem. Now, $\omega$-hugeness is used to describe critical points of <a href="Rank-into-rank" class="mw-redirect" title="Rank-into-rank">I1 embeddings</a>. ## Relative consistency results ### Hugeness of $\omega_1$ In <a href="https://projecteuclid.org/euclid.rmjm/1181073173" class="external autonumber">[2]</a> it is shown that if $\text{ZFC +}$ "there is a huge cardinal" is consistent then so is $\text{ZF +}$ "$\omega_1$ is a huge cardinal" (with the ultrafilter characterization of hugeness). ### Generalizations of Chang's conjecture ### Cardinal arithmetic in $\text{ZF}$ If there is an almost huge cardinal then there is a model of $\text{ZF+}\neg\text{AC}$ in which every successor cardinal is a [Ramsey](Ramsey.md "Ramsey") cardinal. It follows that (1) for all inner models $W$ of $\text{ZFC}$ and every singular cardinal $\kappa$, one has $\kappa^{+W} < \kappa^+$ and that (2) for all ordinal $\alpha$ there is no injection $\aleph_{\alpha+1}\to 2^{\aleph_\alpha}$. This in turn imply the failure of the <a href="index.php?title=Square_principle&amp;action=edit&amp;redlink=1" class="new" title="Square principle (page does not exist)">square principle</a> at every infinite cardinal (and consequently $\text{AD}^{L(\mathbb{R})}$, see <a href="Determinacy" class="mw-redirect" title="Determinacy">determinacy</a>). <a href="https://mathoverflow.net/questions/206090/what-consistency-results-follow-the-assumption-forall-alpha-aleph-alpha1" class="external autonumber">[3]</a> ## In set theoretic geology If $\kappa$ is hyperhuge, then $V$ has lt;\kappa$ many <a href="Ground" class="mw-redirect" title="Ground">grounds</a> (so the <a href="Mantle" class="mw-redirect" title="Mantle">mantle</a> is a ground itself).{% cite Usuba2017 %} This result has been strenghtened to [extendible](Extendible.md "Extendible") cardinals{% cite Usuba2019 %}. On the other hand, it s consistent that there is a [supercompact](Supercompact.md "Supercompact") cardinal and class many grounds of $V$ (because of the indestructibility properties of supercompactness).{% cite Usuba2017 %}