quot;, which in turn means that we would like to have an order defined on cardinals. This order should obey several properties: - If $A\subseteq B$ then $\|A\|\le\|B\|$, - If $\|A\|\le\|B\|$ and $\|B\|\le\|C\|$ then $\|A\|\le\|C\|$, - Every set is not bigger than itself, so $\|A\|=\|A\|$, - If $\|A\|\le\|B\|$ and $\|B\|\le\|A\|$ then either set is no larger than the other, we would like $\|A\|=\|B\|$. This can be done by defining $\|A\|\le\|B\|$ if and only if there exists $f:A\to B$ which is injective. We will show that these properties indeed hold: - If $A\subseteq B$ then $f(a)=a$ is an injective function showing $\|A\|\le\|B\|$. - If $\|A\|\le\|B\|$ and $\|B\|\le\|C\|$ then there are $f:A\to B$ and $g:B\to C$ injective, then $g\circ f:A\to C$ is injective as wanted. - Indeed $f(a)=a$ is a bijection from $A$ onto itself, so $\|A\|=\|A\|$. - Lastly, the Cantor-Schroder-Bernstein theorem ensures us (without using the axiom of choice) the last condition that $\|A\|\le\|B\|$ and $\|B\|\le\|A\|$ imply together $\|A\|=\|B\|$. Using injective functions works fine, however what about surjective functions? In finite subsets the pigeonhole principle ensures us that if there is an injection, but no bijection then there is no surjection. We can also define the surjective relation: $\|A\|\leq^\ast\|B\|\iff\exists f:B\to A\text{ surjective}$ In this ordering, we indeed have that if $A\subseteq B$ then $\|A\|\leq^\ast\|B\|$; as well $\|A\|=^\ast\|A\|$, we even have $\|A\|\leq^\ast\|B\|$ and $\|B\|\leq^\ast\|C\|$ implying $\|A\|\leq^\ast\|C\|$. However we do not have a dual theorem to the Cantor-Schroder-Bernstein theorem, namely it is consistent that $\|A\|<\|B\|$ but $\|B\|\leq^\ast\|A\|$. ## Well orderable cardinals [](Parlour.md) can be well ordered, of course, however infinite sets can be well ordered too. Countable sets are by definition in bijection with [$\omega$](Omega.md "Omega"). Sets of ordinals have a natural order which is a well order, using [](Hartog_number.md) we can deduce that if $\aleph_\alpha$ exists then $\aleph_\alpha^+$ exists, and if we only iterated this set-many times then the increasing union gives us a new cardinal. The result is a proper class of well orderable cardinals. If $\alpha$ is an ordinal, we say that it is an *initial ordinal* if no $\beta<\alpha$ is in bijection with $\alpha$. We can see that initial ordinals are exactly the cardinalities which represent well orderable cardinals, these are the sets which use for [$\aleph$-numbers](Aleph.md "Aleph"). ## Non-well orderable cardinals Assuming the negation of the axiom of choice, we have that some sets cannot be well ordered, and as a result some cardinals are non-$\aleph$ ones. Such examples are infinite <a href="D-finite" class="mw-redirect" title="D-finite">Dedekind finite</a> cardinals, in some models of ZF the real numbers cannot be well ordered, which also forms a non-$\aleph$ cardinal. This article is a stub. Please help us to improve Cantor's Attic by adding information.